Call/WhatsApp/Text: +44 20 3289 5183

Question: Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) write, "In many ways, it is clear that the traditional account of the Scientific Revolution simply does not add up. Indeed, it fails in all three of its basic assumptions." How do Bowler & Morus argue for this claim? Do you agree or disagree and why?

05 Nov 2022,1:10 PM

 

Topic A: Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) write, "In many ways, it is clear that the traditional account of the Scientific Revolution simply does not add up. Indeed, it fails in all three of its basic assumptions." How do Bowler & Morus argue for this claim? Do you agree or disagree and why?

Topic B: Livingstone (2003: 89) writes, “Regional cultures have appropriated scientific knowledge differently according to their sense of self-understanding and put it to different uses. The very meaning of a particular scientific theory or text has shifted from one place to another.” How does Livingstone argue for this claim using the example of Darwin’s theory of evolution? Do you agree or disagree and why?

Expert answer

 

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

 

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

The traditional account of the Scientific Revolution paints a picture of a sudden and dramatic shift in thinking that took place in Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries. This view holds that prior to this period, knowledge was based on superstition and religion, while after this period it was based on reason and empiricism. However, Bowler and Morus (2005: 51) argue that this account is inaccurate and fails to take into account the continuity between the two periods.

 

They point to three main problems with the traditional view. First, it overestimates the role of religion in shaping scientific thought prior to the Scientific Revolution. Second, it underestimates the role of continued religious belief in shaping scientific thought during and after the Scientific Revolution. Third, it fails to take into account the significant scientific advances that were made outside of Europe during this period.

 

Overall, Bowler and Morus make a convincing case that the traditional view of the Scientific Revolution is inaccurate and oversimplified. I agree with their assessment and think that it is important to consider the continuity between the two periods in order to get a more accurate picture of the development of scientific thought.

Stuck Looking For A Model Original Answer To This Or Any Other
Question?


Related Questions

What Clients Say About Us

WhatsApp us